This article transcribes a video essay available here, titled “Cats is a triumph of the cinematic form.”
Cats, the 2019 movie directed by Tom Hooper, represents countless hours of work-power, in likely miserable conditions, assembling what is unmistakably the world’s highest budget work of furry cinema.
Hooper, fresh off the success of the Les Misérables movie adaptation, which I hate, likely had a free reign to interpret as he wished the Andrew Lloyd Webber musical CATS, itself a loose adaptation of T. S. Elliot’s poetry collection “Old Possum’s Book of Practical Cats”. The Webber musical is his standard campy fare, lurid face-paint and costumes in the fashion of Joseph and the Amazing Technicolour Dreamcoat or Phantom of the Opera, two other musicals which had their own dubious route to the big (or small) screen.
Easily the least interesting parts in Cats are where Tom Hooper concedes to the style that won him critical acclaim with Les Misérables and holds a steady close-up of an impassioned face singing a showstopper. Where he’s persuaded away from it, we get Rebel Wilson tearing the head off a cockroach with a human face, Jason Derulo showering himself with milk as a rake of female cats watch in awe, and a succession of cats improbably wearing human clothing seemingly only for fetishistic effect — an even more convincing case for Tom Hooper being prevented from filming close-ups than anything in Les Misérables. Macavity, the cat devil, is introduced with a Batman-like sudden disappearance once he’s off-camera — but the next time he appears he really can teleport and does it constantly for the rest of the film.
The film is determined to see any suggestion that there’s a sexual undertone off at the pass. Over the first thirty minutes, cats present their groins, arch their thighs, tangle round each other almost deliberately so that there’s as much contact with their Barbie-doll under-sections and chests as possible. Every cat is wearing a human-sized collar. Rebel Wilson’s cat bends her tail forward between her legs and swings it like a windmill. Cats wear fursuits, gorge themselves on food and dive into trash cans to rub themselves in waste. When a male character hits a high note, there is a conversation about neutering where Rebel Wilson makes a chop-chop motion with her fingers. As mentioned, Jason Derulo pours milk into his own mouth as he lies back on the floor. The cats devour other, smaller humanoids with a smile and a wink. During his song, there is a lingering shot where Jason Derulo has a furry cat foot inches from mouth with a furry cat foot. By the time three cats are cavorting on a bed together covered in feathers you’re absolutely numb to it, and the film proceeds to get into the plot — and even the plot involves all the cats getting high, having a PG-rated orgy, then lying about groaning for a good minute. Idris Elba’s character is fully dressed for the majority of the film, just so that when he appears sans garments in the climax, you can’t escape any suggestion, Idris Elba is nude now.
As critics have mentioned, the film makes minimal effort to explain who anyone is or what they’re doing. They’re cats, they’re having some kind of event, most of them are going to sing one song, the word Jellicle is involved, get with the program. The cats sing an entire song about the importance of the protagonists’ “real” cat name, but we never find it out. It’s just not for us to know. One member of the main cast is never properly introduced and doesn’t have a song. At one point I thought he was singing about himself but he turned out to be singing about a cat dressed as a male stripper.
Which is fine! It’s fine.
Much of the prerelease buzz around Cats focused on the uncanny appearance of the characters, human faces rotoscoped by hand onto almost-matching CG bodies. What the previews did not reveal, is that the rest of the film compensates for this effect by being equally uncanny, unsettled, and unmoored from conventional notions of filmmaking. The structure of Cats — individual vignettes about the mercurial nature of individual Cats — is forcibly bookended by an overarching plot in which Francesca Hayward’s character, ‘Victoria’ is abandoned by her (full scale human!) owner, such as it were, and falls into the company of a gaggle of cats who immediately begin a chain of often unintelligible songs which continue end-to-end for the rest of the film, save for brief interruptions by the antagonist, Macavity, played by a gurning, scenery-gnawing Idris Elba. The cats hold a yearly competition, we are repeatedly told, where the victor receives a ‘second chance at life’. This plot structure being clamped around the more freeform nature of the musical adds a terrifying air of inevitability to proceedings, and makes the eventual awarding of the prize to Grizabella feel less like the triumph of good nature and compassion and more like “oh crap, gotta foist this ticking bomb off on someone before Idris Elba gets back. The sense of unease and the unknown is shared between the audience and Victoria, but it leaves the more carefree earlier songs feel like they’ve been shot through the sights of a gun. “Stop dancing!” you want to scream at the screen, “Idris Elba is murdering you!”
Between this and the borderline-violent reaction unnamed cats have to the down-and-out Grizabella every time she appears, cat society is deeply unsettling, and that’s before the Taylor-Swift-penned addition to the songbook “Beautiful Ghosts” has appeared, with the haunting refrain “The memories were lost long ago, but at least you have beautiful ghosts”.
Perhaps to provide cover for some less prioritised effects shots, the camera often appears as if in the hand of a drunkard, dipping and rolling with the music in a way that almost induces illness, especially combined with how, over the course of the film, the scope of the visuals slowly narrows and a set of basic images recurs: The theatre door, the bolted milk-parlour, Grizabella in the street, the graveyard entrance, Old Deuteronomy beckons, repeat. One of the most striking visuals, a stairway to heaven summoned by Macavity when he seeks to force Old Deuteronomy to grant him a second life, does not reappear at the denouement. Instead, Grizabella is loaded into a balloon and floated off into the sky.
The protagonist sings of dancing with ghosts; Grizabella is “saved” by being jettisoned into the sky and forgotten. The cats who are kidnapped by Macavity throw Ray Winstone, of Noah fame, into the Thames to drown – and cheer while they do it. Taylor Swift’s cat disappears halfway through the third act. It’s hard not to come to the conclusion that the film is telling us that the cats are in hell, or at least in purgatory. There is a cat devil, but there is no cat god.
Let me be clear about what I am saying: this film is an absolute triumph. It’s utterly bizarre, obeys only its own logic, and I would have eagerly watched another hour of it. Go and see this film.
Please see Cats.
The image of Old Deuteronomy stretching her leg in this article is taken from Twitter user @MrMichaelSwartz’s video.
This article transcribes a video essay available here, titled “Man of Steel is not objectivist.”
The awkward truth, of course, is that we are all Clark Kent — there is always, for all of us, more we could be doing, risks we could be taking, effort we could be expending in the pursuit of being a better person. In the 2012 film Man of Steel, young Clark Kent is grappling with the knowledge that he has extraordinary powers, which he knows he ought to use to help people — given the opportunity. When his school bus crashes into a river, he swims it to the shore, saving everyone on board. A crisis is only narrowly averted; if Clark’s superhuman abilities were attributed to anything other than a mysterious ‘act of god’, his family life would be destroyed. Clark’s extraterrestrial origin is not compatible with a quiet upbringing.
Clark’s dilemma is easily put: he did the right thing, but in doing so he put his family and all their lives in danger, so how can it have been the right thing?. But as he says to his father: “What was I supposed to do? Let them die?”
His father responds: “maybe”.
Some people think that Man of Steel is an objectivist film — objectivism being the mid 20th Century philosophy of Ayn Rand, a philosophy characterised by a radical selfishness and near-total rejection of the existing body of human philosophical thought. Like 80’s philosophical bitcoin. But people who think Man of Steel is objectivist are, to put it bluntly, wrong. And they’re wrong for many different reasons, but the one that interests me most is that — when I first gave it thought — it seemed obvious to me that Man of Steel cannot be an objectivist film because it’s so straightforwardly influenced by existentialist thought.
The issue at hand is whether the questions raised by Man of Steel — questions including “what was I supposed to do?” are questions which reveal a moral flaw at the heart of the film. Is Zack Snyder an objectivist? Possibly. But Clark in Man of Steel would make a poor objectivist hero (At no point, it must be noted, does he consider going in to private enterprise). His villains (chiefly Zod), can’t be said to be collectivists or moralising philanthropists. They’re eugenicists, and Nazis. There is no recourse sought in the film to an objective moral code — in fact, this lack of an objective ethics is often cause for criticism of the film.
Objective morality is represented best in the film by Zod’s Kryptonians, who are explicitly eugenicists.
So, I want to talk through what I consider to be the ethics of the film: existentialist ethics. Man of Steel is full of scenes of anguished choice, absurd decision-making and bad-faith morality. As well, we’ll touch on the ethics of heroism in other action movies and then at the end talk briefly about the bottle city of Kandor and the bad faith of the Kryptonians. But first, this charge levied — that in picking at these moral scabs Man of Steel fatally undermines all morality — was indeed one faced by the existentialists in response to their focus on the actions of the individual
This charge levied, that in picking at these moral scabs Man of Steel fatally undermines all morality, was indeed one faced by the existentialists in response to their focus on the actions of the individual: Simone de Beauvoir characterises the reaction against existentialism as saying that: “To re-establish Man at the heart of his own destiny, they claim, is to repudiate all ethics.”
I have gotten ahead of myself.
Clark saves the workers on the oil rig, but is paralysed by decision. Doing individual good deeds is not an end in itself.
Existentialism is a philosophy of radical freedom popularised in the 19th and 20th Centuries. Well-known philosophers such as Simone de Beauvoir, Jean Paul Sartre and Soren Kierkegaard contributed to existentialist thought. Existentialism breaks from previous western philosophies in its emphasis on the radical freedom of the individual, in part derived from knowledge of the fixed inaccessibility or absence of a God — the idea that we are alone, and our whole lives have to be lived through without ever really knowing what morality “actually is”. Existentialism went out of fashion, both culturally and as a topic of philosophical investigation — but much of what existentialism says about human life and existence cannot be meaningfully said to be wrong.
To paint in broad strokes, the existentialist says that a person is free: that though they may be influenced or pressured or predisposed, in the moment we each ultimately make the call, and there is no-one but ourselves to see into our hearts and evaluate the mode in which we made each decision. For Kierkegaard, who introduced the ‘leap of faith’ into the lexicon, our belief in God and our actions as such would be worthless, if they were not freely chosen in the face of a God who never responds. This absurdity is the true value of faith.
In contrast, almost, much of action cinema and much of superhero cinema is, in being a power fantasy, often really about not having very much freedom at all — if you had to make agonising choices over which there were no clear correct paths, that might take a little of the fun out of it. The origin stories of superheroes are pressure cookers, running the protagonist through a life-altering series of reactions where the choice, when it is put, is more ceremonial in significance than taken in anguish. Spiderman, for example, is imposed on, first by the bite of the radioactive spider, then by the untimely death of his uncle, then by the threat the super-villains pose to his family and friends. He does have a famous great choice to make, where “with great power comes great responsibility” and so on and so forth, but the choice itself is not difficult — Peter has clear and direct moral guidance on this point, he was never going to turn around and say “actually, screw this”.
When Peter’s morality does break down in Spider-man 3, it’s his personal morality, not that relating to his heroics.
Similarly, Iron Man’s Damascene conversion from arms dealer to action robot is not one taken under introspection. His life as an arms dealer reaches a dramatic pre-ordained end: violence begets violence. His choice is between dying as an arms dealer or executing righteous justice on his jailers — some choice! And this is the power fantasy aspect of it — it’s a shared human fantasy, of being found in the righteous spotlight, compelled and justified in doing or saying something we’d otherwise feel ashamed of, because it’s something rude, or something disproportionate, or something illegal.
Expressing these power fantasies in film isn’t necessarily a bad thing, either morally or in terms of making a great movie: in Assault on Precinct 13, a rag-tag bunch of individuals are forced by circumstance and morality into mounting a last-ditch defence of a police station against seemly never-ended waves of punk kids. To this end, they kill indiscriminately for most of the film’s runtime. Much of the thrill of the movie revolves around seeing — forced in the moment — whether or not the criminal characters, who are implicitly not part of the moral contract the rest of the characters adhere to, will in fact be morally compelled in this way.
Of course, this pattern doesn’t fit every superhero, or every action protagonist. Aside from anything else, there’s just lots of them, and they’re used to tell all sorts of stories. Even Batman, for all that people like to fantasise about him as a power fantasy, is really just too weird a concept to be un-ironically identified with in that way. In Die Hard, Bruce Willis repeatedly choses to reintroduce himself into the sequence of events in a way which in the sequels will be transliterated into belief in his own hyper-competence, but in the original feels more like personal instability.
Living the dream.
Which brings us to consider again the condition of Clark Kent in Man of Steel. We see him drifting, taking several jobs. He saves the lives of men on a burning oil rig — but he also has a power trip on this petty asshole in the bar. We see that Clark feels obliged to use his abilities to do good in the world, but we see him struggle with translating that obligation into action. With great power comes great responsibility — in the abstract — but to who is this responsibility due, and how? Even in seemingly innocuous decisions like taking the job on the fisher boat, he causes one of his new colleagues to risk his life — just by existing, he is placed in situations where others feel obligations to him; there is no vacuum for him to perform idealised good deeds in.
In this way, Man of Steel preempts this traditional introduction to the action protagonist, where we meet them on the cusp of an event that will transform them into a hero. Clark is already a hero in so much as he can be a hero; he has been a hero since he was a child and raised that bus from the river; but that doesn’t help him decide what to do right now. The issue that he questioned as a child is still entirely relevant: he knows that he ought to do that which is moral, but how to decide the most moral path? We can see in the opening sequence that he has become an ascetic, a nomad, a drifter. He has no extraneous human attachments that we see. His life is consumed entirely by these small moments of heroism and the balance of danger that comes with them.
Existentialism has a word for the the difficulty of choice: anguish. Having to act, and so choose one of several paths which cannot be known to be the correct one beforehand. In Existentialism is a Humanism,Sartre says:
“When a man commits himself to anything, fully realising that he is not only choosing what he will be, but is thereby at the same time a legislator deciding for the whole of mankind — in such a moment a man cannot escape from the sense of complete and profound responsibility.” — Jean Paul Sartre
And this is the dominant mode in Man of Steel, from the bus rescue through to the climax. Clark cannot escape a sense of complete and profound responsibility. He must choose. For humanity, he chooses as a man to give himself up to the Kryptonians. As a Kryptonian, he chooses to abandon his people and their one cruel shot at restoring their former glory. And he receives no shielding from the consequences of these choices. His family’s lives are placed in danger. Hundreds of people die in collapsing buildings and explosions. To save humanity, he ends Krypton with his own hands.
This breaks more than a fantastical “no kill” rule; it leaves Clark alone in the universe of his people.
This is a painful choice to make, even though it is the right one. And so when, as a child, Clark demands of his father — who has taught him to be good, who has taught him: great power, great responsibility: what was I meant to do? Do I owe more to the lives I saved, or the lives of my family? Lives in the present, or the lives I will save as a grown Superman? What was I meant to do, let them die? There is no good answer Pa Kent can give. The choices are not going to get easier from hereon in. Clark has to consider — maybe he should have let them drown — because, as trivial as this particular case seems in the aftermath, choices are coming for which there will be no-one who can help. This is the lesson Pa Kent dies teaching Clark: not just that doing good will involve hard choices, but that doing good will involve unfair choices and ridiculous choices and hopeless choices. Clark will have to kill Zod, ending his entire race, because Zod refuses to stop senselessly killing. That is an absurd choice, and yet, morally, it is the right thing to do.
I think people see objectivism lurking behind these thoughts because they make heroism fundamentally un-enjoyable. Seen in clear light, it stops being a power fantasy and starts being a burden no-one could possibly want. And so, presented with situations where the easy, power fantasy fulfilling option is the selfish one, they see a movie which wants them to be selfish.
There’s a concept in the Superman comics called the bottle city of Kandor. The idea is that the robot Brainiac shrank an entire city from Krypton before its destruction, incorporating all of its culture and people, into a bottle, and Superman later fights the robot and retrieves the bottle. Then, aghast, he repeatedly fails to return the city to its proper size without causing some kind of corresponding catastrophe on Earth. This is generally interpreted as a ‘great burden’ type deal, the one line which even Superman is not powerful enough to cross. In Man of Steel, this concept is revisited in the codex, the dead sum of Kryptonian culture with which Clark is entrusted. The codex could be used — by Zod — to restore Krypton on earth — at only the cost of all of humanity.
A bottle city…
The Kryptonians, before the destruction of their world, are portrayed as the beneficiaries of eugenics: the codex is used to ensure that every Kryptonian is bred exactly for his role, and no new life is permitted outside of this. In this way, the character of every Kryptonian is drawn into the codex. They are defined fully before they even exist, and so restoring Krypton is simply a case of calling them back into being.
I think the transition from the bottle city to the codex, which is literally a skull, makes explicit the ghoulish quality of the exchange: to trade in the living for the dead, an ascendent culture for one which has already served to extinct itself. Between the codex and Zod, the villains in Man of Steel are not the foes of objectivism, but the foes of existentialism. In the codex, the idea that a people can have their worth defined prior to their choices in life, and in Zod the exemplar of a man who attributes all his successes and failures to preordained destiny.
…and a skull.
Zod’s account to Clark, of his inbuilt, fixed character and quality, is a fantasy. Zod claims himself as born a military leader, never deviating from that path — even as he commits the act of rebellion. He rejects that he made that choice, and he rejects that he made the choice to kill Jor-el, even though he visibly does so in anger. At the end of the film, when all hope is lost, he claims that his every action, no matter how violent, exists to serve Krypton —
“I exist only to protect Krypton. That is the sole purpose for which I was born. And every action I take, no matter how violent or how cruel, is for the greater good of my people. And now I have no people. My soul. That is what you have taken from me.”
— but how, then, does he justify his final actions, once Krypton (calcified in the form of the Codex) has been destroyed? Zod is choosing, even as he claims not to choose. Zod is thus the mirror counterpart to Clark, the actor in bad faith, denying his choices even as he makes them.
“The genius of Proust is the totality of the works of Proust; the genius of Racine is the series of his tragedies, outside of which there is nothing. Why should we attribute to Racine the capacity to write yet another tragedy when that is precisely what he did not write? In life, a man commits himself, draws his own portrait and there is nothing but that portrait.” — Jean Paul Sartre
The Kryptonians and Kryptonian society want to deny that, as individuals, they are free, and also that, as individuals, they are abandoned. Kryptonians have their behaviour determined and implicitly excused by their genetic programming. The worth of any given Kryptonian is privileged to be the worth of all Kryptonian society. In this way, from this vantage point, Krypton demands the opportunity to write another tragedy — Zod demands the opportunity to write another tragedy. And because he is attributing his desires and choices to this external source, denying that he has influence over them, he denies himself any end other than the one he receives: stripped of all that provided him meaning, he acts entirely out of spite and malice.
Zod strikes out of anger, already defeated.
Ayn Rand defines her philosophy, in the appendix to Atlas Shrugged, like this:
“My philosophy, in essence, is the concept of man as a heroic being, with his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life, with productive achievement as his noblest activity, and reason as his only absolute.” — Ayn Rand
I dunno, your mileage may vary, but I don’t really see any of that in Man of Steel. Clark certainly doesn’t see his own happiness as the moral purpose of his life in any way, and his two father figures both sacrifice themselves for their faith in a nameless future.In one of the most famous quotes from Existentialism is a Humanism, Sartre defines in contrast the existentialist creed: “man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world — and defines himself afterwards”
And this, I think, is the essence of Man of Steel. Clark defines himself.
To return in the last to de Beauvoir, arguing against the criticism that existentialism is a philosophy of what might be called moral relativism:
“far from God’s absence authorising all license, the contrary is the case, because man is abandoned on the earth, because his acts are definitive, absolute engagements. He bears the responsibility for a world which is not the work of a strange power, but of himself, where his defeats are inscribed, and his victories as well. A God can pardon, efface, and compensate. But if God does not exist, man’s faults are unforgivable.” — Simone de Beauvoir